sábado, 16 de febrero de 2019

Philosophy postures in systematics: Which is the best approach to do science?


The diversity of viewpoints and positions around all study topics is very important in the science world. This variety thoughts allows to evaluate different perspectives of the same problem using different methodologies, and generate a great framework (Pavese and De Bièvre, 2015). Nevertheless, science must go hand in hand with objectivity (Hanna, 2004), therefore we must ask ourselves, which is the best approach to carry out scientific research?

Firstly, we must located on a radical idea: Falsification (Popper, 2002a). For this Popperian vision we only know what we don’t know, thus, being literals, it’s impossible discover absolutes trues, and we can only corroborate and falsify hypotheses (Popper, 2002b). My viewpoint about Popper’s falsification in science is: we must use it only as a reminder of why we shouldn't take for granted the current theories, thus, the search of knowledge remains standing. However, beyond this last idea, I don’t think Popper’s thought has a direct applicability nowadays.

Now, we can understand that the impulse of science is to understand more and more things, but, how do we trust what we know? The knowledge search through science needs statistics, and frequentists with their classical interpretation of probability based on finite observations of experimental events, have contributed greatly (Bayarri and Berger, 2004). Nevertheless, this vision can generate problems like wrong interpretations or the impossibility of  assign probabilities to unrepeatable events (Bayarri and Berger, 2004; Box and Tiao, 1992). Moreover, Bayesian vision doesn’t have these problems being a better option because probabilities are based on a prior  knowledge, it means, there is always uncertainly because we never know all facts but we can assign a value of how much knowledge have about results (Briggs, 1999; Schoot et al., 2014). 

For this reason, I must emphasize that we can’t know everything but we can know a lot, therefore, methods based on the Bayesian philosophy, give us, in my opinion, the best approximation to the scientific truth, especially in systematics, where the evolutionary history is a large set of inferences.


References

- Bayarri, M. J. and Berger, J. O. (2004). The interplay of Bayesian and frequestist analysis. Statistical Science, 19(1), 58-80.
- Briggs, A.H. (1999). A Bayesian approach to stochastic cost‐effectiveness analysis. Health Econ.18, 257-261. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1099-1050(199905)8:3<257::AID-HEC427>3.0.CO;2-E
- Box, G. E. and Tiao, G. C. (1992). Bayesian inference in statistical analysis. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
- Hanna, J. (2004). The Scope and Limits of Scientific Objectivity. Philosophy of Science71(3), 339-361. doi:10.1086/421537
- Pavese, F. and De Bièvre, P. (2015). Fostering diversity of thought in measurement science. In F. Pavese, W. Bremser, A. Chunovkina, N. Fischer and A. Forbes (Ed.), Advanced Mathematical and Computational Tools in Metrology and Testing X (pp. 1–8). Singapore: World Scientific
- Popper, K. (2002a). The logic of scientific discovery. London, England: Routledge. doi:https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203994627
Popper, K. (2002b). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. London, England: Routledge. doi:https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203538074
- Schoot, R., Kaplan, D., Denissen, J., Asendorpf, J. B., Neyer, F. J. and Aken, M. A. (2014). A Gentle Introduction to Bayesian Analysis: Applications to Developmental Research. Child Dev, 85, 842-860. doi:10.1111/cdev.12169







2 comentarios:

Andres Ordoñez dijo...

Good evening my classmate,
I will make just one commentary, and its aim is defended Popper's philosophy in phylogenetic analyses. It's complete false your opinion "I don’t think Popper’s thought has a direct applicability nowadays", parsimony analysis is based on Popper (Farris, 1983), and some authors have an important discussion for justified or fit Popper's thought to Likelihood analyses (Helfenbein, 2005; Rieppel, 2003; Farris et al., 2001; Faith, 1992). And there are some articles in other disciplines applying Popper (Bailey, 2018; Robergs, 2017).
If you make this kind of rude affirmations you should have references as articles or notes from relevant authors.

Farris, J. (1983). The logical basis of phylogenetic analysis.
Rieppel, O. (2003). Popper and systematics. Systematic Biology, 52(2), 259-271.
Farris, J. S., Kluge, A. G., & Carpenter, J. M. (2001). Popper and likelihood versus “Popper*”. Systematic Biology, 50(3), 438-444.
Bailey, R. (2018). Education in the open society-Karl Popper and schooling. Routledge.
Helfenbein, K. G., & DeSalle, R. (2005). Falsifications and corroborations: Karl Popper’s influence on systematics. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, 35(1), 271-280.
Faith, D. P., & Cranston, P. S. (1992). Probability, parsimony, and Popper. Systematic Biology, 41(2), 252-257.
Robergs, R. A. (2017). Lessons from Popper for science, paradigm shifts, scientific revolutions and exercise physiology. BMJ open sport & exercise medicine, 3(1), e000226.

Liz Villabona-Arenas dijo...

Good morning,

Even if his approach in academic philosophy has been widely discussed, Karl Popper had become recognised as one of the most important philosophers of the 20th Century. His influence is reflected in the number of people who have applied a popperian approach to their own concerns like Imre lakatos, Paul Feyerabend, Peter Medawar, John Carew Eccles, Ernst Gombrich or Stephen Hawking[1,2]. Having a popperian vision remains as a valid starting point to this day and can't be overlook.

On the other hand, you must correlate and explain more clearly why choosing a Bayesian approach is better according to your philosophy.

1. Bailey, R. Education in the open society. 2 2-37 (Ashgate, 2002).
2. Halbwachs, H., Simmel, J. & Bässler, C. Tales and mysteries of fungal fruiting: How morphological and physiological traits affect a pileate lifestyle. Fungal Biology Reviews 30, 36-61 (2016).