To start you have to know the concept of this word in
the biological context, so, homology is the existence of shared ancestry between a pair of
structures, or genes, in different species. But around the
application of this concept exists a large discussion. Moreover, (Brigandt, 2003) propose the idea of ‘radiation of a concept’, in
which explain that homology can be different depending of the biological field
in where is used. For example, he exposes four fields, molecular,
developmental, evolutionary and comparative biology. First, in the last ones, the
goals are the comparison and even taxonomy of species and characters and the
explanation of descent with modification. In phylogenetic systematics, homology
is a diagnostic for monophyletic groups, which helps to characterize taxa. The
role of molecular homology is the inference of information about the molecular
behavior of genes and proteins. Finally, (Brigandt,
2003) concludes that the goal in evolutionary
developmental biology is to figure out how and why certain structures emerge in
different ontogenies. If you want a detailed review of the most famous concepts
of homology you can go to (Patterson,
1982).
Here, we are going to focus in an
evolutionary and phylogenetic field in which you can found a definition from
homology as synapomorphy (Patterson,
1982) and the concept that reveals ancestry
and descent with modification. Nevertheless, (dePinna,
1991) cited Wagner 1989 and Roth 1988, who disagree with the idea
of homology as synapomorphy of (Patterson,
1982), argued that is a broader and extensive concept that should not be
restricted in such way. On the other hand, (dePinna, 1991) also quote to deQueiroz 1985, he argued that homology
is a notion that applies to instantaneous morphologies, while synapomorphy
(according to his definition) applies to ontogenetic transformations that
characterize monophyletic groups (his view of characters).
About the relation of homology
and sinapomorphy, that does not have to be only attributable to
Patterson 1982, (Eldredge &
Cracraft, 1980) said that “….
homology can be conceptualized simply as synapomorphy (including
symplesiomorphy [...])”. However respect to this affirmation is obvious noted
that symplesiomorphic similarities are homologous; it is a synapomorphy at a
higher level. So, for example you can found two types of homology in that
sense.
Taxic homology implies a hierarchy of groups, hypotheses
of monophyly, and constitutes a statement about generality of characters, or
"sameness" of attributes. And transformational homology is concerned
with the transformation of one structure into another.
But how recognize the existence of a homology; some
authors said that there are two classes of homology, primary and secondary, the
first for (Agnarsson &
Coddington, 2008) is a kind of background assumption or prior
knowledge that you can based in similarity, and for (dePinna, 1991)is the (theory-laden
but untested) supposition that two parts are the same by inheritance. In this
way, (Agnarsson &
Coddington, 2008) express “In systematic biology homology hypotheses are
typically based on points of similarity and tested using congruence. Indeed
testing similarity is the only way to test the homology of characters, as
congruence only tests their states”. However, you can say that the homology is
inherent to the character and not to their states.
So, I think that if
the homology hypotheses pass the test of congruence and it fit to the topology
then they are right.
(Rieppel & Kearney, 2002) reviewed the topic
of primary homology and argued that things can be similar to greater or lesser
degrees, at different scales, and in different independent ways. The secondary
homology have resisted the test of congruence, emerged as synapomorphies on a
cladogram (dePinna, 1991).
The problem of
primary homology is not confined to morphological data. Aligning base positions
in “homologous” sequences across different taxa is a crucial phase in molecular
analysis, but one method in particular, “Direct Optimization”(Wheeler, 1996), search optimal
trees via direct optimization, hence varying dynamically the primary homology
hypotheses. From the three
tests of homology proposed to date (similarity, conjunction and congruence)
only congruence serves as a test in the strict sense (dePinna, 1991), in addition is complicated establish homologies
based only in similarity and in prior knowledge of a single character, in
contrast, you have to integrate some characters and parameters that help to
identify true homologies. However, conjunction is unquestionably an indicator
of non-homology, but it does not say when a homology appears.
On the side of molecular homology there are three
disjoint subtypes of homology.
Orthology: is that
relationship where sequence divergence follows speciation. In (Fitch, 2000).
The true phylogeny obtained from this sequences is
exactly the same as the true phylogeny of the organisms from which the
sequences were obtained. Only orthologous sequences have this property.
Paralogy is defined as that condition where sequence divergence
follows gene duplication. In (Fitch,
2000).
Mixing paralogous with orthologous sequences it is
posible obtain a tree that has the correct phylogeny for the sequences but not
for the taxa from which they derive; a gene tree is not necessarily a species
tree.
Xenology is defined
as that condition (horizontal transfer) where the history of the gene involves
an interspecies transfer of genetic material. In (Fitch,
2000).
________________________________________________________________________________
Agnarsson, I., & Coddington, J. A. (2008).
Quantitative tests of primary homology. Cladistics, 24(1), 51–61.
doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.2007.00168.x
Brigandt, I. (2003). Homology in comparative, molecular, and evolutionary
developmental biology: the radiation of a concept. Journal of Experimental
Zoology. Part B, Molecular and Developmental Evolution, 299(1),
9–17. doi:10.1002/jez.b.36
Eldredge, N., & Cracraft, J. (1980). Phylogenetic Patterns and the
Evolutionary Process (method and theory in comparative biology). Retrieved from
http://ciib.unam.mx:8080/xmlui/handle/123456789/6819
Fitch, W. M. (2000). Homology. Trends in Genetics, 16(5),
227–231. doi:10.1016/S0168-9525(00)02005-9
Patterson, C. (1982). Morphological characters and homology. In Problems
of Phylogenetic Reconstruction (pp. 21–74).
Pinna, M. C. C. (1991). CONCEPTS AND TESTS OF HOMOLOGY IN THE CLADISTIC
PARADIGM. Cladistics, 7(4), 367–394. doi:10.1111/j.1096-0031.1991.tb00045.x
Rieppel, O., & Kearney, M. (2002). Similarity. Biological Journal
of the Linnean Society. doi:10.1046/j.1095-8312.2002.00006.x
Wheeler, W. C. (1996). Optimization Alignment: the End of Multiple
Sequence Alignment in Phylogenetics? Cladistics, 12, 1–9.
doi:10.1006/clad.1996.0001
No hay comentarios:
Publicar un comentario